CLAT Exam  >  CLAT Questions  >  In recent decades, few ideas have received as... Start Learning for Free
In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possess by virtue of their inherent dignity and that exist independently of legal or social recognition. This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally. For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).
Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute. Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors. In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’ vis-à-vis powerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.
Q. Which of these options describe the argument?
  • a)
    Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.
  • b)
    The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.
  • c)
    Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.
  • d)
    A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignity is an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.
Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer?
Verified Answer
In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that o...
The author has not given an absolute definition relating to human rights .He has taken the concepts of status and described the relation with the human rights.
View all questions of this test
Explore Courses for CLAT exam

Similar CLAT Doubts

In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.What is thediscrepancyin the given argument?

In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.How has the author explained the concept of dignity with regard to human rights in the above argument?

In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.What is the conclusion of the author regarding human rights?

In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of the following, if true, provides the most support for the argument above?

Top Courses for CLAT

In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer?
Question Description
In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer? for CLAT 2024 is part of CLAT preparation. The Question and answers have been prepared according to the CLAT exam syllabus. Information about In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer? covers all topics & solutions for CLAT 2024 Exam. Find important definitions, questions, meanings, examples, exercises and tests below for In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer?.
Solutions for In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer? in English & in Hindi are available as part of our courses for CLAT. Download more important topics, notes, lectures and mock test series for CLAT Exam by signing up for free.
Here you can find the meaning of In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer? defined & explained in the simplest way possible. Besides giving the explanation of In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer?, a detailed solution for In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer? has been provided alongside types of In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer? theory, EduRev gives you an ample number of questions to practice In recent decades, few ideas have received as much attention as that of human rights. But what, exactly, are human rights? A popular answer characterises them as entitlements that all human beings possessby virtue of their inherent dignityand that exist independently of legal or social recognition.This definition, which draws a conceptual link between human rights and dignity, is prominent in scholarly circles, human-rights documents and political discourse more generally.For instance, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) of 1948 refers to dignity multiple times, and so do the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966).Despite its popularity, this way of connecting dignity and human rights is uninformative at best and counter-productive at worst. It is uninformative because the notion of inherent dignity is opaque. It is often just a placeholder for whichever human attribute grounds human rights, with different philosophical traditions disagreeing on the relevant attribute.Reference to inherent dignity is also counter-productive, since it pushes the debate on human rights into deep metaphysical waters and distracts from their political function: placing constraints on the conduct of powerful actors.In this article, I propose a new understanding of the relationship between dignity and human rights—one that reinforces, rather than undermines, their power-taming function. To do so, I distinguish between dignity as a status, involving distinctive normative demands (status dignity), and dignity as an inherent property of individuals, which purportedly justifies ascribing a certain status to them (inherent dignity). Status dignity and inherent dignity need not always accompany each other: one may hold status dignity by virtue of possessing properties other than inherent dignity. Definitions of human rights have focused on inherent dignity. I argue that the focus should shift to status dignity—particularly, the status dignity of individuals’vis-à-vispowerful sovereign entities—leaving open what inherent human property grounds or justifies that status.Q.Which of these options describe the argument?a)Human rights are often defined as standards of treatment that human beings command by virtue of their inherent dignity.b)The notion of dignity is slippery. In recent years, there has been much discussion concerning its genesis and proper meaning.c)Notion of (status) dignity may be appropriately applied not only to individual agents, but to states as well.d)A status an entity possesses, comprising stringent normative demands where as the inherent dignityis an inherent property of an entity, possession of which is said to justify the attribution of a given status to it.Correct answer is option 'B'. Can you explain this answer? tests, examples and also practice CLAT tests.
Explore Courses for CLAT exam

Top Courses for CLAT

Explore Courses
Signup for Free!
Signup to see your scores go up within 7 days! Learn & Practice with 1000+ FREE Notes, Videos & Tests.
10M+ students study on EduRev